Research
My research is driven by questions about how our cognitive structures and the social world interact. I am especially interested in in evidence-resistance and the dynamics of belief revision, in particular in social and political contexts. You can read more about general themes in my research in this (slightly outdated) interview. My PhilPeople page links directly to all my published papers (both published versions and PDFs of penultimate drafts).
The papers below cover a range of topics. Here are major thematic clusters:
Evidence-responsiveness, evidence-resistance, and belief: In “Resistant beliefs, responsive believers” (Journal of Philosophy, in press) and “Why think that belief is evidence-responsive?” (What is Belief?, OUP, in press), I offer new arguments for the claim that, if you believe something, then you have the capacity to change that attitude in the light of evidence. A central focus is accounting for the obvious fact that it’s often very hard to change people’s minds. In “Epistemic norms on evidence-gathering” (co-authored with Elise Woodard, Philosophical Studies, 2023), we discuss the epistemology of one major source of evidence-resistance, namely, failures to gather relevant evidence.
Epistemic styles: In “Epistemic styles” (Philosophical Topics, 2021), I introduce the notion of epistemic styles to account for divergences in how agents interact with evidence. In a work-in-progress paper, I argue that time spent on social media inculcates distinctive epistemic styles, as opposed to only changing the evidence we have (the focus of public discussions of misinformation).
Neurodiversity and interactions with evidence in psychiatric contexts: I have a series of papers applying the theoretical work above to psychiatric contexts - often taken to be limit cases of irrational or non-standard interactions with evidence. In “Delusional evidence-responsiveness” (Synthese, 2021), I argue that delusions are responsive to evidence, and therefore can count as beliefs. In “Delusion and evidence” (Routledge Handbook on the Philosophy of Delusion, in press), I describe how delusions relate to evidence, focusing on similarities with ordinary cases. In “Epistemic style in OCD” (a short commentary, Philosophy, Psychology, and Psychiatry, 2023)), I suggest the notion may be useful to explain inquiry and reasoning in OCD. In a paper under review, I suggest that delusion-supporting reasoning in schizophrenia constitutes an epistemic style, and argue that this makes it substantially intelligible.
Identity labels and essentialism: In “‘That’s all you really are’”, Liz Camp and I offer a characterization of what is involved in centering social identities in thought and interaction, offering an alternative to models that assume agents have essentialist beliefs in such cases and detailing implications for addressing such behavior. In “Playing with labels”, we consider one mechanism involved in centering social identities - identity labels -, examine their cognitive and social role, and then focus on the distinctive profile of playful uses of such labels. (This paper has the most entertaining examples of all my papers.)
For what it’s worth, the articles I am proudest of are: “Resistant beliefs, responsive believers”; “Epistemic styles”; and “Playing with labels”.
Publications
-
Abstract: Beliefs can be resistant to evidence. Nonetheless, the orthodox view in epistemology analyzes beliefs as evidence-responsive attitudes. I address this tension by deploying analytical tools on capacities and masking to show that the cognitive science of evidence-resistance supports rather than undermines the orthodox view. In doing so, I argue for the claim that belief requires the capacity for evidence-responsiveness. More precisely, if a subject believes that p, then they have the capacity to rationally respond to evidence bearing on p. Because capacities for evidence-responsiveness are fallible and may be masked, beliefs can be held in the face of counter-evidence. Indeed, I will argue that our best science of belief supports the claim that evidence-resistant beliefs result from masks on evidence-responsiveness capacities. This account of belief not only allows for resistance to evidence, but provides us with a framework for describing and explaining actual cases of evidence-resistance.
-
Identity labels are widely thought to undermine agency by essentializing groups, flattening individual distinctiveness, and enforcing discrimination. While we take these worries to be well-founded, we argue that they result from a particular practice, of using labels to rigidly label others. We identify an alternative practice, of playful self-labeling, and argue that it can function as a tool for combating oppression by expressing and enhancing individual and collective agency.
-
(Draft)
Abstract: We consider cases where we treat others as “nothing more” than some social type (e.g. a woman or a Muslim). What cognitive states lead to this behavior? The standard view holds that essentialist beliefs---beliefs that attribute essences to social groups---lie behind this treatment. We argue against this view. Agents can center identities in more intuitive ways. In standard cases, agents do so by regulating their thinking using frames---e.g. slogans, memes, or images. Specifically, they use frames that focus attention on these social identities and associated stereotypes. Agents' thinking can be shaped by frames without their believing that these frames accurately describe reality. This view has important practical implications for what strategies we should employ to combat discriminatory, objectifying, and dehumanizing treatment of others.
-
This chapter focuses on how delusions relate to evidence. I give some reasons to think that people typically have evidence for their delusions, and that the evidence they have against them is often overstated. I draw on this discussion to consider whether delusions are evidentially supported and epistemically rational. Finally, I discuss implications for the nature of delusion, responsibility, and treatment and suggest directions for future research. A central upshot is that what we should say about the epistemic standing of delusions depends substantively on our positions in epistemology, in particular, on the debate between internalists and externalists about evidence.
-
I offer a novel argument for a version of the view that belief is constitutively responsive to evidence, one that appeals to the notion of capacities. I do so by developing the Sellarsian idea that the concept of belief functions to mark the space of reasons in a non-intellectualist and naturalistic direction. The resulting view of belief does justice to the role of belief in social interactions, joint deliberation, and rational persuasion, while including evidence-resistant beliefs and animal beliefs as genuine beliefs, and has a range of further benefits for epistemology and philosophy of mind.
-
(Penultimate Version; Handout; Tongue-in-cheek summary for New Work in Philosophy Substack)
Abstract: We argue that there are epistemic, rather than merely practical or moral, norms on evidence-gathering. In doing so, we develop a test for determining whether a norm is epistemic by looking at our practices of accountability. With epistemic norms on evidence-gathering, we can defend epistemology against charges on which it looks myopic. And, with the test we develop, we can get clear on the connection between the zetetic and the epistemic.
-
Commentary on Pablo Hubacher Haerle’s paper “Is OCD Epistemically Irrational?”. I argue for expanding our assessment of rationality in OCD by considering a wider range of epistemic parameters and how they fit together.
-
(Penultimate version; 5-minute video; Portuguese translation!)
Abstract: Epistemic agents can respond to the same evidence in different ways. I argue that, to explain this phenomenon, we need to appeal to epistemic styles: ways of interacting with evidence that express unified sets of epistemic values, preferences, goals, and interests. The paper introduces the notion of epistemic styles and develops a systematic account of their nature. The account has implications for normative epistemology, the scope of epistemic agency, and understanding disagreement and the value of cognitive diversity.
-
(Penultimate version; published version; short blog post)
Abstract: I argue that delusions are evidence-responsive in the sense that subjects have the capacity to rationally respond to counter-evidence on their delusions. The extreme evidence-resistance of delusions is a consequence of powerful masking factors on these capacities, such as strange perceptual experiences, motivational factors, and cognitive biases. This view makes room for holding both that belief is constitutively evidence-responsive and that delusions are beliefs, dissolving long-standing debates about delusions and the nature of belief. And it has important implications for the study and treatment of delusions.
Work in progress
-
(Draft available upon request)
I argue that identity-protective reasoning can be epistemically rational. Specifically, it is epistemically rational when at the service of defending true beliefs against misleading counter-evidence, which (more) often happens for members of marginalized groups. In addition to defending this view, I draw connections to standpoint epistemology and also draw out methodological suggestions for existing projects in mainstream political epistemology.
-
(Draft available upon request)
Online misinformation is often blamed for contemporary epistemic pathology by spreading misinformation, i.e., false or misleading evidence. I argue that the internet makes a different, underappreciated contribution to epistemic pathology: it reshapes users’ epistemic agency. Specifically, I argue that the algorithmic web (the social-media-centered internet that has become dominant since the early 2010s) inculcates and habituates agents to new, and often epistemically detrimental, epistemic styles. Our online lives change how we interact with evidence, not just what evidence we have. I discuss key design features of major online platforms that contribute to this, and sketch one concrete example of an epistemic style promoted by online engagement. Finally, I argue that this under-explored phenomenon is worrisome from both political and epistemic perspectives.
-
(Draft)
Abstract: Reasoning that supports delusions in schizophrenia appears to lie beyond the bounds of sense. I argue against this view by analyzing such reasoning as constituting a distinctive epistemic style, one that makes sense by the lights of underlying epistemic values.
-
Abstract: Individual beliefs often push back against structural reform, leading such reform to fail. Troublingly, beliefs that play this role often resist the evidence, persisting in the face of structural change. This poses a problem for structuralism, which prescribes large-scale structural change without considering how to get individuals to abandon such resistant social beliefs. I argue that the structuralist has resources to address the problem of resistant social beliefs. Specifically, I argue that large-scale changes to the shape of social networks can lead to the abandonment of resistant social beliefs, addressing even forms of active psychological resistance to belief change such as identity-protective reasoning. This solution to the problem of resistant social beliefs has significant implications for the debate between structuralists and individualists. In particular, it shows that careful attention to human psychology and proposing structural interventions are compatible.
Some Recent and Upcoming Talks
University of Utah Philosophy Department Colloquium, Salt Lake City, USA, Fall 2024 TBD
Meeting of the Portuguese Society for Analytic Philosophy, Lisbon, Portugal, 10-12 July 2024
Episteme Workshop, Rhodes, Greece, 4-5 July 2024
Logos Seminar, University of Barcelona, Barcelona, Spain, 31 May 2024
Princeton Political Epistemology Workshop, Princeton, USA, 6 April 2024